The first RFRA was a 1993 federal
law signed by president Bill Clinton. It unanimously passed the House of
Representatives, where it was sponsored by then-congressman Chuck Schumer, and
sailed through the Senate on a 97-3 vote. How many laws are that obvious, that
well-supported by left and right? Before Indiana, nineteen states had substantially identical laws
on their books. Illinois’ version was enacted with the “yea” vote of
then-state-Senator Barack Obama.
The law reestablished a balancing
test for courts to apply in religious liberty cases (a standard had been used
by the Supreme Court for decades). RFRA allows a the government by its
rules, laws, ordinances, etc., to "substantially burden" a person's
free exercise of religion only if the law furthers a "compelling
governmental interest" and uses the "least restrictive means of furthering
that compelling governmental interest."
So much of the debate seems to
focus on one person or group imposing their views on another. Let me illustrate:
Since when should Ann have the right under law to force Bob to behave in conformity with her moral views and participate in her conduct? RFRA would protect Bob from having to do what Ann demands, unless the government has some compelling reason to force everyone like Bob to always do what Ann is asking. This is not a “gay” issue, but the “gay rights” militants take Ann’s side, that the government should enforce Ann’s demand on Bob.Two people are each minding their own business. They have nothing to do with each other. Ann approaches Bob and says, "Hey, I demand that you do something for me that violates your sincerely held religious beliefs, beliefs that one or more major religions held for thousands of years."Bob replies, "Wow, I'd like to serve you, but could you ask someone else? Other people will help you with that. But for me, I think it might displease God if I did it. You are free to do what you want, but please don't ask me to join you."Ann responds: "You bigot! I'm suing you and taking everything you have!"
But let’s play this out. At what point would the
militants (and all politicians who are now complaining about Bill Clinton’s
RFRA and the state versions enacted since) disagree with Ann? What if Ann asks Bob
to:
- sing in Ann’s night club, since Bob is a singer?
- sing at Ann’s Mosque, since Bob is a singer?
- cater at Ann’s lewd bachelorette party, since Bob is a caterer?
- officiate Ann’s gay wedding, since Bob is an Imam at the local Mosque?
- take nude photos of Ann, since Bob is a photographer?
- print a porn magazine, since Bob runs a print shop?
- do the cutting for Ann’s animal sacrifice, since Bob is a butcher?
- abort Ann’s child, since Bob is an OBGYN?
Should Ann be able to legally force Bob in each of these cases? If Bob has a sincerely held conviction against the
activities, he would not have to participate under RFRA unless the
government shows some compelling reason that all Bobs in all circumstances
must yield to all similarly-situated Anns in the world. Perhaps the government
could demonstrate that, and would back Ann in her demand. Maybe in the case of
baking a cake to celebrate a gay wedding, the government has a compelling
interest in forcing all Bobs to do so, while in the case of animal sacrifice it
does not. Perhaps in the case of singing at the Mosque it does, and in the abortion case it does not.
But these are the questions under RFRA, not the answers.
I encourage you to read the following essay from
C.S. Lewis. He saw the liberals’ inconsistency in England more than 50 years
ago. They said sexual freedom should be given equal footing with other freedoms,
but the real proposal is to elevate it to a new and higher right that trumps
all others. His insights are, as always, profound and quite applicable to the
situation in which we find ourselves.
Curt
****************************************************
Have We No Right to Happiness?
C.S. Lewis
“After all,” said Clare. “they had a right to
happiness.”
We were discussing something that
once happened in our own neighborhood. Mr. A. had deserted Mrs. A. and got his
divorce in order to marry Mrs. B., who had likewise got her divorce in order to
marry Mr. A. And there was certainly no doubt that Mr. A. and Mrs. B. were very
much in love with one another. If they continued to be in love, and if nothing
went wrong with their health or their income, they might reasonable expect to
be very happy.
It was equally clear that they were
not happy with their old partners. Mrs. B. had adored her husband at the
outset. But then he got smashed up in the war. It was thought he had lost his
virility, and it was known that he had lost his job. Life with him was no
longer what Mrs. B. had bargained for. Poor Mrs. A., too. She had lost her looks—and
all her liveliness. It might be true, as some said, that she consumed herself
by bearing his children and nursing him through the long illness that
overshadowed their earlier married life.
You mustn’t, by the way, imagine
that A. was the sort of man who nonchalantly threw a wife away like the peel of
an orange he’d sucked dry. Her suicide was a terrible shock to him. We all knew
this, for he told us so himself. “But what could I do?” he said. “A man has a
right to happiness. I had to take my one chance when it came.”
I went away thinking about the
concept of a “right to happiness.”
At first this sounds to me as odd as
a right to good luck. For I believe—whatever one school of moralists may
say—that we depend for a very great deal of our happiness or misery on
circumstances outside all human control. A right to happiness doesn’t, for me,
make much more sense than a right to be six feet tall, or have a millionaire
for your father, or to get good weather whenever you want to have a picnic.
I can understand a right as a
freedom guaranteed me by the laws of the society I live in. Thus, I have a
right to travel along the public roads because society gives me that freedom;
that’s what we mean by calling the roads “public.” I can also understand a
right as a claim guaranteed me by the laws, and correlative to an obligation on
someone else’s part. If I have a right to receive $100 from you, this is
another way of saying that you have a duty to pay me $100. If the laws allow
Mr. A. to desert his wife and seduce his neighbor’s wife, then, by definition,
Mr. A. has a legal right to do so, and we need bring in no talk about
happiness.
But of course that was not what
Clare meant. She meant that he had not only a legal but a moral right to act as
he did. In other words, Clare is—or would be if she thought it out—a classical
moralist after the style of Thomas Aquinas, Grotius, Hooker and Locke. She
believes that behind the laws of the state there is a Natural Law.
I agree with her. I hold this
conception to be basic to all civilization. Without it, the actual laws of the
state become an absolute, as in Hegel. They cannot be criticized because there
is no norm against which they should be judged.
The ancestry of Clare’s maxim. “They
have a right to happiness,” is august. In words that are cherished by all
civilized men, but especially by Americans, it has been laid down that one of
the rights of man is a right to “the pursuit of happiness.” And now we get to
the real point.
What did the writers of that august
declaration mean?
It is quite certain what they did
not mean. They did not mean that man was entitled to pursue happiness by any
and every means—including, say, murder, rape, robbery, treason and fraud. No
society could be built on such a basis.
They meant “to pursue
happiness by all lawful means”; that is, by all means which the Law of Nature
eternally sanctions and which the laws of the nation shall sanction.
Admittedly this seems at
first to reduce their maxim to the tautology that men (in pursuit of happiness)
have a right to do whatever they have a right to do. But tautologies, seen
against their proper historical context, are not always barren tautologies. The
declaration is primarily a denial of the political principles which long
governed Europe; a challenge flung down to the Austrian and Russian empires, to
England before the Reform Bills, to Bourbon France. It demands that whatever
means of pursuing happiness are lawful for any should be lawful for all that
“man,” not men of some particular cast, class, status or religion, should be
free to use them. In a century when this is being unsaid by nation after nation
and party after party, let us not call it a barren tautology.
But the question as to
what means are “lawful”—what methods of pursuing happiness are either morally
permissible by the Law of Nature or should be declared legally permissible by
the legislature of a particular nation—remains exactly where it did. And on
that question I disagree with Clare. I don’t think it is obvious that people
have the unlimited “right to happiness” which she suggests.
For one thing, I believe
that Clare, when she says “happiness,” means simply and solely “sexual
happiness.” Partly because women like Clare never use the word “happiness” in
any other sense. But also because I never heard Clare talk about the “right” to
any other kind. She was rather leftist in her politics, and would have been
scandalized if anyone had defended the actions of a ruthless man-eating tycoon
on the ground that his happiness consisted in making money and he was pursuing
his happiness. She was also a rabid teetotaler; I never heard her excuse an
alcoholic because he was happy when he was drunk.
A good many of Clare’s
friends, and especially her female friends, often felt—I’ve heard them say
so—that their own happiness would be perceptibly increased by boxing her ears.
I very much doubt if this would have brought her theory of a right to happiness
into play.
Clare, in fact, is doing
what the whole western world seems to me to have been doing for the last 40-odd
years. When I was a youngster, all the progressive people were saying, “Why all
this prudery? Let us treat sex just as we treat all our other impulses.” I was
simple-minded enough to believe they meant what they said. I have since
discovered that they meant exactly the opposite. They meant that sex was to be
treated as no other impulse in our nature has ever been treated by civilized
people. All the others, we admit, have to be bridled. Absolute obedience to
your instinct for self-preservation is what we call cowardice; to your
acquisitive impulse, avarice. Even sleep must be resisted if you’re a sentry.
But every unkindness and breach of faith seems to be condoned provided that the
object aimed at is “four bare legs in a bed.”
It is like having a
morality in which stealing fruit is considered wrong—unless you steal
nectarines.
And if you protest
against this view you are usually met with chatter about the legitimacy and
beauty and sanctity of “sex” and accused of harboring some Puritan prejudice
against it as something disreputable or shameful. I deny the charge. Foam-born
Venus … golden Aphrodite … Our Lady of Cyprus… I never breathed a word against
you. If I object to boys who steal my nectarines, must I be supposed to
disapprove of nectarines in general? Or even of boys in general? It might, you
know, be stealing that I disapproved of.
The real situation is skillfully
concealed by saying that the question of Mr. A’s “right” to desert his wife is
one of “sexual morality.” Robbing an orchard is not an offense against some
special morality called “fruit morality.” It is an offense against honesty. Mr.
A’s action is an offense against good faith (to solemn promises), against
gratitude (toward one to whom he was deeply indebted) and against common
humanity.
Our sexual impulses are thus being
put in a position of preposterous privilege. The sexual motive is taken to
condone all sorts of behavior which, if it had any other end in view, would be
condemned as merciless, treacherous and unjust.
Now though I see no good reason for
giving sex this privilege, I think I see a strong cause. It is this.
It is part of the nature of a strong
erotic passion—as distinct from a transient fit of appetite—that makes more
towering promises than any other emotion. No doubt all our desires makes
promises, but not so impressively. To be in love involves the almost
irresistible conviction that one will go on being in love until one dies, and
that possession of the beloved will confer, not merely frequent ecstasies, but
settled, fruitful, deep-rooted, lifelong happiness. Hence all seems to be at
stake. If we miss this chance we shall have lived in vain. At the very thought
of such a doom we sink into fathomless depths of self-pity.
Unfortunately these promises are
found often to be quite untrue. Every experienced adult knows this to be so as
regards all erotic passions (except the one he himself is feeling at the
moment). We discount the world-without-end pretensions of our friends’ amours
easily enough. We know that such things sometimes last—and sometimes don’t. And
when they do last, this is not because they promised at the outset to do so.
When two people achieve lasting happiness, this is not solely because they are
great lovers but because they are also—I must put it crudely—good people;
controlled, loyal, fair-minded, mutually adaptable people.
If we establish a “right to (sexual)
happiness” which supersedes all the ordinary rules of behavior, we do so not
because of what our passion shows itself to be in experience but because of
what it professes to be while we are in the grip of it. Hence, while the bad
behavior is real and works miseries and degradations, the happiness which was
the object of the behavior turns out again and again to be illusory. Everyone
(except Mr. A. and Mrs. B.) knows that Mr. A. in a year or so may have the same
reason for deserting his new wife as for deserting his old. He will feel again
that all is at stake. He will see himself again as the great lover, and his
pity for himself will exclude all pity for the woman.
Two further points remain.
One is this. A society in which
conjugal infidelity is tolerated must always be in the long run a society
adverse to women. Women, whatever a few male songs and satires may say to the
contrary, are more naturally monogamous than men; it is a biological necessity.
Where promiscuity prevails, they will therefore always be more often the
victims than the culprits. Also, domestic happiness is more necessary to them
than to us. And the quality by which they most easily hold a man, their beauty,
decreases every year after they have come to maturity, but this does not happen
to those qualities of personality —women don’t really care two cents about our
looks—by which we hold women. Thus in the ruthless war of promiscuity women are
at a double disadvantage. They play for higher stakes and are also more likely
to lose. I have no sympathy with moralists who frown at the increasing crudity
of female provocativeness. These signs of desperate competition fill me with
pity.
Secondly,
though the “right to happiness” is chiefly claimed for the sexual impulse, it
seems to be impossible that the matter should stay there. The fatal principle,
once allowed in that department, must sooner or later seep through our whole
lives. We thus advance toward a state of society in which not only each man but
every impulse in each man claims carte blanche. And then, though our
technological skill may help us survive a little longer, our civilization will
have died at heart, and will—one dare not even add “unfortunately”—be swept
away.
This
was reportedly the last published article by C.S. Lewis before his death. He
must be rolling over in his grave.
No comments:
Post a Comment